Back home by the North Sea

As we usually do at the end of term, Beth and I have returned home to North Norfolk. Throughout the academic year, I greatly miss the North Sea from coast to countryside. In the past I’ve written about the coastal footpaths we’ve come to know intimately; the secret gardens and ponds off the path, with many hidden nooks etched into the landscape for a quiet picnic or some outdoor reading; the little cottage that we lived in for many years, where the clock seemed to tick slower; the sand dunes and the cliffs towering over the beaches; the rolling heathland where Shetland ponies roam free; and the poetry of tall Scotch pines seamlessly blending with farmland and rich marshes. It’s a romantic vision, I admit. It’s a land we know deeply, such that as we return each year from university we notice many small and intricate changes to the tangled ditches that line familiar country lanes; the assorted growth of wildflowers and the poppies that border the rolling fields; not to mention the forest paths we frequent where new saplings seem to be constantly breaking the soil. There are so many changes and developments in a year as the land takes new shape.

***

Aside from studying birds and other wildlife, and when not engaged in spontaneous philosophical and scientific enquiry, a reoccurring topic of discussion this week has been sociological. I haven’t taken too many pictures of the towns and villages, nor of the people, but for every eloquent description of the countryside it is interesting to also think about the sociological dimension of life here.

Beth and I spent important formative years growing up in North Norfolk, and we know first-hand how young locals might eventually yearn for more opportunities and possibilities than what can be offered by the local towns and villages. In our visit to Sheringham we spoke to a young lad at one of our favourite chip shops. He was quite sweet, working in what was probably his new summer job. When we mentioned in passing that we used to live in the area he commented in agreement that it is difficult because there aren’t many opportunities. We call this lack opportunity in rural England and the eventual forced migration ‘the brain drain’. It gives description to how young people feel they must leave rural areas to find economic opportunity, perhaps most prominently university graduates. This brain drain relates to the common, if not universal paradox in many western countries as far as I can tell: urbanisation versus rural life.

To my mind, there hasn’t been a single period of British government (left or right on the spectrum) that has successfully confronted this paradox, although some more than others have certainly exacerbated the issue over the years. In North Norfolk I think it is fair to say that for a place that is so tranquil its sociological dimension can feel restrictive and absent of future. The reality is in the juxtaposition. The beauty of the landscape and the richness of rural life on the one hand, and then the creaking public infrastructure, rural poverty, lack of opportunity and social mobility, along with lower wages combined with higher living costs on the other. Then there is the ongoing issue of the loss of small farms, the struggle of small business, and the erosion of important civic assets like access to land and well-connected transportation networks. (I imagine these issues stretch across the entire country).

In the right situation with a well-paid job nearby or with one in the nearest city; established money; the special circumstance of successfully establishing a small business; or economically viable farming (not at all an easy thing to do nowadays with many farmers selling off their businesses); one could live here in great peace and enjoy a genuine slice of heaven. Otherwise, it can easily be a desperate situation with few channels for basic work and with fewer opportunities in which one might secure a decent living. (I remember reading a sociological study where the youth of old industrial cities and mining towns offered similar accounts).

I would say East Anglia shares similar sociological features as most counties ranging north from the Midlands to the Scottish boarder. For every coastal town or rural village with a healthy economy, there is another that is quite obviously deteriorating. In the heart of North Norfolk, with its glorious scenes, quaint flint-stone cottages, and well-off neighbourhoods – of which I often speak poetically – there are also obvious signs of poverty. Towns like Holt are a good example. From the view of an outside observer Holt has the appearance of an affluent neighbourhood; but that general appearance of affluence can be misleading when it comes to the particular realities of people that call it home. Generally, a lot of the wealth does not seem to be sourced, or kept, locally. Many people have holiday homes in this area and therefore reside here only part-time or less, bringing their wealth from London and elsewhere. I think this partly contributes to the affluent appearance. Its impact is noticeable in many little details of life, like the quality of the roads, perhaps because a lot of the money is not actually taxed here; or in how the buildings on the high street are owned by only one or two companies.

I am quite sensitive to people. I like watching and observing. After a certain amount of time, it becomes easy to distinguish a local from a part-time resident or a tourist. The distinguishing features between the locals, part-time residents, and temporary holiday-goers can be much more obvious in towns like Cromer, North Walsham, and parts of King’s Lynn. When passing through Cromer it is possible to see local families wait in line at the foodbank as tourists pass with ice creams after enjoying a day on the beach. In many cases, poverty seems to be entrenched; such that it is not surprising when the Office for National Statistics releases a report indicating massive income disparities in this area. Extrapolate across the whole of England, and one finds a fairly straightforward explanation for Brexit and other recent political trends, with people in rural areas feeling abandoned or perhaps even completely forgotten. All it takes is appropriately directed political rhetoric to exploit the underlying currents of resentment and frustration.

But that’s enough observation and reflection for now. My main purpose was to share some photographs of the countryside. Perhaps next time I will focus more on writing about the many different towns and villages, with their unique histories and characteristics, and about the people that live in this area. I can then also focus on taking more pictures from that perspective.

***

The most popular castle in Norfolk is Norwich Castle. Outside of Norwich in rural Norfolk there were over 20 other castles built during the Middle Ages. The other day we returned to Baconsthorpe Castle, which has a very interesting history. I hadn’t been here for almost 10 years, so it was lovely to see it again.

The main court yard would have been full with residences and stables. You can see a bit of it behind me, although much of the structure has been lost over centuries.

The castle is situated next to a pond. There were lots of baby ducks and baby swans swimming in it, but we didn’t manage to get a good picture. Here is one photograph of the pond facing away from the castle’s courtyard.

The lane to get to the castle cuts through a number of fields. It makes for a painting in-itself. Quintessential Norfolk.

This picture reminds me a lot of the family dairy farm. It was nice to visit. There wasn’t time to see the cows on this occasion, but I did take some photos of the fields that Beth and I used to walk through.

We had lunch in the orchard under one of the apple trees.

Weybourne beach is a place we like to have picnic dinners. Watching the seabirds and the fishermen is one of my favourite pastimes. It’s a place where many locals will spend the evening with a comfortable chair, a good book, and a bottle of wine.

The sea was especially calm this day. We managed to capture a few lovely photos.

Beth and I will sometimes search the shingle beaches for cool pebbles and cobbles. I’ve been experimenting with taking more focused photographs, and this is one of the cobbles that I think looks good.

One of our favourite forests in North Norfolk is captured below. I’ve written about this forest a few times in the past. It is one of the first places we visit whenever we return to Holt. We used to go for walks here a few times a week, and it is always interesting to compare the growth over the years.

Here I am walking down one of my favourite footpaths that runs under a canopy of trees. On the other side of the gate is an entrance to the heath.

Below are some pictures of the heath, which has changed dramatically in the last 10 years. We used to be able to see very far down into the valley, but the goss has grown so much that this is no longer possible. In recent visits we’ve also spotted more garden snakes than usual (in fact, we never used to see any at all!), suggesting perhaps that their population has grown. I am curious as to why. Maybe there has been a decline in the population of birds of prey?

Here we are having a sit down.

Beth did take one image of Sheringham high street on our way to the beach beneath the cliffs.

Here is a photo of the beach and the cliffs.

Sheringham Golf Club is situated just a top these cliffs. It’s a beautiful links course that I was looking forward to play if not for an injury.

One of the most beautiful places on planet Earth, as far as I am concerned, is Holkham beach.

Here is a tile gallery of a few more of my favourite pictures.

It was especially hot one day we were there, so we receded to the forest. The tall Scotch pines provided lots of shade. The treeline also made for a nice photo.

Finally, a picture of Beth and I having a stop at a countrypark. We’ve never been here before, and I was excited to learn that it had a fresh water lake.

Double Field Theory as the double copy of Yang-Mills

1. Introduction

A few weeks ago I came across this paper [DHP] on Double Field Theory and the double copy of Yang-Mills. Its result is most curious.

As a matter of introduction, recall how fundamental interactions in nature are governed by two kinds of theories: On the one hand, Einstein’s theory of relativity. On the other hand we have Yang-Mills theory, which provides a description of the gauge bosons of the standard model of particle physics. Yang-Mills is one example of gauge theory; however, not all gauge theories must necessarily be of Yang-Mills form. In a very broad picture view, gravity is also a gauge theory. This can be most easily seen in the diffeomorphism group symmetry.

Of course, Yang-Mills is the best quantum field theory that we have; it yields remarkable simplicity and is at the heart of the unification of the electromagnetic force and weak forces as well as the theory of the strong force, i.e., quantum chromodynamics. Similarly one might think that, given gravity is an incredibly symmetric theory, it should also yield a beautiful QFT. It doesn’t. When doing perturbation theory, even at quadratic order things already start to get hairy; but then at cubic and quartic order the theory is so complicated that attempting to do calculations with the interaction vertices becomes nightmarish. So instead of a beautiful QFT, what we actually find is incredibly complicated.

In this precise sense, on a quantum level there is quite an old juxtaposition between gauge theory in the sense of Yang-Mills (nice and simple) versus gravity (a hot mess). In other parts, the two can be seen to be quite close (at least we have have a lot of hints that they are close). Indeed, putting aside gauge formulations of gravity, even simply under the gauge theory of Lorentz symmetries we can start to draw a comparison between gravity and Yang-Mills, and this has been the case since at least the 1970s. Around a similar time gauge theory of super Poincare symmetries produced another collection of hints. And, one of the most important examples without question is the holographic principle and the AdS/CFT correspondence.

Yet another highly fruitful way to drill down into gauge-gravity, especially over the last decade, has followed the important work of Bern-Carrasco-Johansson in [BCJ1] and [BCJ2]. Here, a remarkable observation is made: gravity scattering amplitudes can be seen as the exact double copy of Yang-Mills amplitudes, suggesting even further a deeply formal and profoundly intimate relationship between gauge theory and gravity.

Schematically put, following the double copy technique it is observed that gravity = gauge x gauge. This leads to the somewhat misleading statement that gravity is gauge theory squared.

A lot goes back to the KLT relations of string theory. The general idea of the double copy method is that, from within perturbation theory, Yang-Mills (and gauge theories in general) can be appropriately constructed so that their building blocks obey a property known as color-kinematics duality. (This is, in itself, a fascinating property worthy of more discussion in the future. To somewhat foreshadow what is to come, there were already suspicions in the early 1990s that it may relate to T-duality, which one will recall is a fundamental symmetry of the string). Simply put, this is a duality between color and kinematics for gauge theories leaving the amplitudes unaltered.

For instance, to understand the relation between gravity and gauge theory amplitudes at tree-level, we can consider a gauge theory amplitude where all particles are in the adjoint color representation. So if we take pure Yang-Mills

\displaystyle  S_{YM} = \frac{1}{g^2} \int \text{Tr} F \wedge \star F \ \ (1)

there is an organisation of the n-point L-loop gluon amplitude in terms of only cubic diagrams

\displaystyle  \mathcal{A}_{YM}^{n,L} = \sum \limits_i \frac{c_i n_i}{S_i d_i}, \ \ (2)

where {c_i} are the colour factors, {n_i} the kinetic numerical factors, and {d_i} the propagator. Then the color-kinematic duality states that, given some choice of numerators, such that if those numerators are known, it is required there exists a transformation from any valid representation to one where the numerators satisfy equations in one-to-one correspondence with the Jacobi identity of the color factors,

\displaystyle  c_i + c_j + c_k = 0 \Rightarrow n_i + n_j + n_k = 0

\displaystyle  c_i \rightarrow -c_i \Rightarrow n_i \rightarrow -n_i. \ \ (3)

So, as the kinematic numerators satisfy the same Jacobi identities as the structure constants do, for some choice of numerators (from what I understand the choice is not unique), we can obtain the gravity amplitude. For example, given double copy {c_i \rightarrow n_i} it is possible to obtain an amplitude of {\mathcal{N} = 0} supergravity

\displaystyle  \mathcal{A}_{\mathcal{N}=0}^{n,L} = \sum \limits_i \frac{n_1 n_i}{S_i d_i}, \ \ (4)

where one will notice in the numerator that we’ve striped off the colour and replaced with kinematics, and where the supergravity action is

\displaystyle  S_{\mathcal{N}=0} = \frac{1}{2\kappa^2} \int \star R - \frac{1}{d-2} d\psi \wedge \star d\psi - \frac{1}{2} \exp(- \frac{4}{d-2}\psi) dB \wedge \star dB. \ \ (5)

In summary, the colour factors that contribute in the gauge theory appear on equal footing as the purely kinematical numerator factors (functions of momenta and polarizations), and all the while the Jacobi identities are satisfied. When all is said and done, the hot mess of a QFT in the gravity theory can be related to the nicest QFT in terms of Yang-Mills.

But notice that none of what has been said has anything to do with a description of physics at the level of the Lagrangian. For a long time, some attempts were made but there was no reason to think the double copy method should work at the level of an action. As stated in [Nico]: ‘no amount of fiddling with the Einstein-Hilbert action will reduce it to a square of a Yang-Mills action.’ Although many attempts have been made, with some notable results, this question of applying the double copy method on the level of the action takes us to [DHP].

In this paper, the authors use the double copy techniques to replace colour factors with a second set of kinematic factors, which come with their own momenta, and it ultimately leads to a double field theory (see past posts for discussion on DFT) with doubled momenta or, in position space, a doubled set of coordinates. In other words, the double copy of Yang-Mills theory (at the level of the action) yields at quadratic and cubic order double field theory upon integrating out the duality invariant dilaton.

When I first read this paper, the result of obtaining the background independent DFT action was astounding to me. In what follows, I want to quickly review the calculation (we’ll only consider the quadratic action, where the Lagrangian remains gauge invariant).

2. Yang-Mills / DFT – Quadratic theory

Start with a gauge theory of non-abelian vector fields in D-dimensions

\displaystyle  S_{YM} = -\frac{1}{4} \int \ d^Dx \ \kappa_{ab} F^{\mu \nu a} F_{\mu \nu}^{b}, \ \ (6)

with the field strength for the gauge bosons {A_{\mu}^{a}} defined as

\displaystyle  F_{\mu \nu}^{a} = \partial_{\mu} A^{a}_{\nu} - \partial_{\nu}A^{a}_{\mu} + g_{YM} f^{a}_{bc}A_{\mu}^{b} A_{\nu}^{c}. \ \ (7)

Here {g_{YM}} is the usual gauge coupling. The {f^{a}_{bc}} term denotes the structure constants of a compact Lie group (i.e., in this case a non-Abelian gauge group). This group represents the color gauge group, and we define {a,b,...} as adjoint indices. The invariant Cartan-Killing form {\kappa_{ab}} lowers the adjoint indices such that {f_{abc} \equiv \kappa_{ad}f^d_{bc}} is antisymmetric.

Expanding the action (3) to quadratic order in {A^{\mu}} and then integrating by parts we find

\displaystyle  -\frac{1}{4} \int d^{D}x \ \kappa_{ab} \ (-2 \Box A^{\mu a} A_{\mu}^{b} + \partial_{\mu}\partial^{\nu} A^{\mu a}A_{\nu}^b). \ \ (8)

Pulling out {A^{\mu a}} and the factor of 2, we obtain the second-order action as given in [DHP]

\displaystyle  S_{YM}^{(2)} = \frac{1}{2} \int d^{D}x \ \kappa_{ab} \ A^{\mu a}(\Box A^{b}_{\mu} - \partial_{\mu} \partial^{\nu} A^b_{\nu}). \ \ (9)

To make contact with the double copy formalism, we next move to momentum space with momenta {k}. Define {A^{a}_{\mu}(k) = 1/(2\pi)^{D/2} \int d^D x \ A_{\mu}^{a}(x) \exp(ikx)}. In these notes we use the shorthand {\int_k := \int d^{D} k}. In [DHP], the convention is used where {k^2} is scaled out, which then allows us to define the following projector

\displaystyle  \Pi^{\mu \nu}(k) \equiv \eta^{\mu \nu} - \frac{k^{\mu} k^{\nu}}{k^2}, \ \ (10)

where we have the Minkowski metric {\eta_{\mu \nu} = (-,+,+,+)}.

Proposition 1 The projector defined in (10) satisfies the identities

\displaystyle  \Pi^{\mu \nu}(k)k_{\nu} \equiv 0, \ \text{and} \ \Pi^{\mu \nu}\Pi_{\nu \rho} = \Pi^{\mu}_{\rho}. \ \ (11)

Proof: The second identity is trivial, while the first identity can be found substituting (10) in (11) and recalling we’ve scaled out {k^2}. \Box

The first identity in (11) implies gauge invariance under the transformation

\displaystyle  \delta A^{a}_{\mu}(k) = k_{\mu}\lambda^a(k), \ \ (12)

where the gauge parameter {\lambda^a(k)} is defined as an arbitrary function.

3. Double copy of gravity theory

Proposition 2 The double copy prescription of gravity theory leads to double field theory.

Proof: Begin by replacing the color indices {a} by a second set of spacetime indices {a \rightarrow \bar{\mu}}. This second set of spacetime indices then corresponds to a second set of spacetime momenta {\bar{k}^{\bar{\mu}}}. For the fields {A^a_{\mu}(k)} in momentum space, we define a new doubled field

\displaystyle  A^a_{\mu}(k) \rightarrow e_{\mu \bar{\mu}}(k, \bar{k}). \ \ (13)

Next, following the double copy formalism, a substitution rule for the Cartan-Killing metric {\kappa_{ab}} needs to be defined. In [DHP], the authors propose that we replace this metric with a projector carrying barred indices such that

\displaystyle  \kappa_{ab} \rightarrow \frac{1}{2} \bar{\Pi}^{\bar{\mu} \bar{\nu}}(\bar{k}). \ \ (14)

Notice, this expression exists entirely in the barred space.

Remark 1 (Argument for why (14) is correct) It is argued that the replacement (14) is derived from the double copy rule at the level of amplitudes. Schematically, one can consider a gauge theory amplitude of the form {\mathcal{A} = \Sigma_i n_i c_i / D_i}, where {n_i} are kinematic factors, {c_i} are colour factors, and {D_i} denote inverse propagators. Then, in the double copy, replace {c_i} by {n_i} with {D_i \sim k^2}. This means that {k^2} may be scaled out as before, leaving only the propagator to be doubled.

Making the appropriate substitutions, we obtain a double copy action for gravity of the form

\displaystyle  S_{grav}^{(2)} = - \frac{1}{4} \int_{k, \bar{k}} \ k^2 \ \Pi^{\mu \nu}(k) \bar{\Pi}^{\bar{\mu}\bar{\nu}}(\bar{k}) \ e_{\mu \bar{\mu}}(-k, -\bar{k})e_{\nu \bar{\nu}}(k, \bar{k}). \ \ (15)

The structure of this action is really quite nice; in some ways, it is what one might expect as it is very reminiscent of the structure of the duality symmetric string.

To make the doubled nature of the action (15) more explicit, define doubled momenta {K = (k, \bar{k})}, and, just as the duality symmetric string, treat {k, \bar{k}} on equal footing. It now seems arbitrary whether there is {k^2} or {\bar{k}^2} at the front of the integrand. In any case, unlike the measure factor for the duality symmetric string which, in momentum space, takes the form {k, \tilde{k}}, the asymmetry of (15) is resolved by imposing

\displaystyle  k^2 = \bar{k}^2, \ \ (16)

which one might notice is just the level-matching condition. To obtain DFT, the imposition of this constraint is necessary (indeed, just like it is in pure DFT).

Remark 2 (More general solutions) The solution {k = \bar{k}} should be familiar from studying the linearised theory. However, here exists more general solutions and it might be interesting to think more about this matter.

It is fairly straightforward to see that under

\displaystyle  \delta e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} = k_{\mu}\bar{\lambda}_{\bar{\nu}} + \bar{k}_{}\bar{\nu}\lambda_{\mu} \ \ (17)

the action (15) is invariant. Now we have two gauge parameters dependent on doubled momenta.

Upon writing out the projectors (11) and then imposing the level-matching condition (16), we can use the metric to lower indices. Then taking the product with the {e} fields, we find the action (15) to take the following form:

\displaystyle  S_{grav}^{(2)} = -\frac{1}{4} \int \ \int_{k, \bar{k}} (k^{2}e^{\mu \bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} - k^{\mu}k^{\rho}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}e^{\bar{\nu}}_{\rho} - \bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}\bar{k}^{\bar{\sigma}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}e^{\mu}_{\bar{\sigma}} + \frac{1}{k^2}k^{\mu}k^{\rho}\bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}\bar{k}^{\bar{\sigma}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}e_{\rho \bar{\sigma}}). \ \ (18)

Already one can see this looks very similar to the background independent quadratic action of DFT. To get a better comparison, we can Fourier transform to doubled position space. In doing so, it is observed that every term transforms without a problem except the last term which results in a non-local piece. The trick, as noted in [DHP], is to introduce an auxiliary scalar field {\phi(k, \bar{k})} (i.e., the dilaton).

Doing these steps means we can first rewrite (18) as follows

\displaystyle  S_{grav}^{(2)} = -\frac{1}{4} \int \ \int_{k, \bar{k}} (k^{2}e^{\mu \bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} - k^{\mu}k^{\rho}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}e^{\bar{\nu}}_{\rho} - \bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}\bar{k}^{\bar{\sigma}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}e^{\mu}_{\bar{\sigma}} - k^2 \phi^2 + 2\phi k^{\mu}\bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}). \ \ (19)

By using the field equations for {\phi}

\displaystyle  \phi = \frac{1}{k^2} k^{\mu}\bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} \ \ (20)

or, alternatively, using the redefinition

\displaystyle  \phi \rightarrow \phi^{\prime} = \phi - \frac{1}{k^2} k^{\mu}\bar{k}^{\bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} \ \ (21)

we then get back the non-local action (18).

Remark 3 (Maintaining gauge invariance) What’s nice is that (19) is still gauge invariant, which can be checked using also the gauge transformation for the dilaton {\delta \phi = k_{\mu}\lambda^{\mu} + \bar{k}_{\bar{\mu}}\bar{\lambda}^{\bar{\mu}}}.

Now Fourier transforming (19) to doubled position space, we define in the standard way {\partial_{\mu} / \partial x^{\mu}} and {\bar{\partial}_{\bar{\mu}} = \partial / \partial \bar{x}^{\bar{\mu}}}. We also of course obtain the usual duality invariant measure. The resulting action takes the form

\displaystyle  S_{grav}^{(2)} = \frac{1}{4} \int d^D x \ d^D \bar{x} \ (e^{\mu \bar{\nu}}\Box e_{\mu \bar{\nu}} + \partial^{\mu}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}\partial^{\rho}e_{\rho}^{\bar{\nu}}

\displaystyle  + \bar{\partial}^{\bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}\bar{\partial}^{\bar{\sigma}}e^{\mu}_{\bar{\sigma}} - \phi \Box \phi + 2\phi \partial^{\mu}\bar{\partial}^{\bar{\nu}}e_{\mu \bar{\nu}}. \ \ (22)

\Box

This is the standard quadratic double field theory action. As such, it maintains gauge invariance – notice, we haven’t had to impose a gauge condition and the only extra field introduced was the dilaton.

Very cool.

References

[BCJ1] Z. Bern, J.J. M. Carrasco, and H. Johansson, New Relations for Gauge-Theory Amplitudes. [0805.3993 [hep-ph]].

[BCJ2] Z. Bern, J.J. M. Carrasco, and H. Johansson, Perturbative Quantum Gravity as a Double Copy of Gauge Theory. [1004.0476 [hep-th]].

[BJH] R. Bonezzi, F. Diaz-Jaramillo, O. Hohm, The Gauge Structure of Double Field Theory follows from Yang-Mills Theory. [2203.07397 [hep-th]]

[DHP] F. Dıaz-Jaramillo, O. Hohm, and J. Plefka, Double Field Theory as the Double Copy of Yang-Mills. [2109.01153 [hep-th]].

[Nico] H. Nicolai, “From Grassmann to maximal (N=8) supergravity,” Annalen Phys. 19, 150–160 (2010).

*Cover image: Z. Bern lecture notes, Gravity as a Double Copy of Gauge Theory.

Notes on string theory #2: The relativistic point particle (pp. 9-11)

1. Introduction

In Chapter 1 of Polchinski’s textbook, we start with a discussion on the relativistic point particle (pp. 9-11).

String theory proposes that elementary particles are not pointlike, but rather 1-dimensional extended objects (i.e., strings). In fact, string theory (both the bosonic string in Volume 1 of Polchinski and the superstring that comprises much of Volume 2) can be seen as a special generalisation of point particle theory. But the deeper and more modern view is not one that necessarily begins with point particles and then strings, instead the story begins with branes. In that a number of features of string theory are shared by the point particle – as we’ll see in a later note, the point particle can be obtained in the limit the string collapses to a point – the bigger picture is that both of these objects can be considered as special cases of a p-brane.

We refer to p-branes as p-dimensional dynamical objects that have mass and can have other familiar attributes such as charge. As a p-brane moves through spacetime, it sweeps out a latex (p+1)-dimensional volume called its worldvolume. In this notation, a 0-brane corresponds to the case where p = 0. It simply describes a point particle that, as we’ll discuss in this note, traces out a worldline as it propagates through spacetime. A string (whether fundamental or solitonic) corresponds to the p = 1 case, and this turns out to be a very special case of p-branes (for many reasons we’ll learn in following notes). Without getting too bogged down in technical details that extend well beyond the current level of discussion, it is also possible to consider higher-dimensional branes. Important is the case for p = 2, which are 2-dimensional branes called membranes. In fact, the etymology for the word ‘brane’ can be viewed as derivative from `membrane’. As a physical object, a p-brane is actually a generalisation of a membrane such that we may assign arbitrary spatial dimensions. So, for the case {p \geq 2} , these are p-branes that appear in string theory as solitons in the corresponding low energy effective actions of various string theories (in addition to 0-branes and 1-branes).

In Type IIA and Type IIB string theories, which again is a subject of Volume 2, we see that there is entire family of p-brane solutions. From the viewpoint of perturbative string theory, which is the primary focus of Volume 1, solitons as p-branes are strictly non-perturbative objects. (There are also other classes of branes, such as Dp-branes that we’ll come across soon when studying the open string. The more complete picture of D/M-brane physics, including brane dynamics, is anticipated to be captured by M-theory. This is a higher dimensional theory that governs branes and, with good reason, is suspected to represent the non-perturbative completion of string theory).

In some sense, one can think of there being two equivalent ways to approach the idea of p-branes: a top-down higher dimensional view, or from the bottom-up as physical objects that generalise the notion of a point particle to higher dimensions. But given an introductory view of p-branes, perhaps it becomes slightly more intuitive why in approaching the concept of a string in string theory we may start (as Polchinski does) with a review of point particle theory. Indeed, it may at first seem odd to model the fundamental constituents of matter as strings. Indeed, it could seem completely arbitrary and therefore natural to ask, why not something else? But what is often missed, especially in popular and non-technical physics literature, is the natural generalising logic that leads us to study strings in particular. These are remarkable objects with remarkable properties, and what Polchinski does so well in Volume 1 is allow this generalising logic to come out naturally in the study of the simplest string theory: bosonic string theory.

In this note, we will construct the relativistic point particle action as given in p.10 (eqn. 1.2.2) and then work through the proceeding discussion in pages 10-11. The quantisation of the point particle is mentioned several pages later in the textbook, so we’ll address that topic then. In what follows, I originally also wanted to include notes on the superparticle and its superspace formulation (i.e., the inclusion of fermions to the point particle theory of bosons), as well as introduce other advanced topics; but I reasoned it is best to try to keep as close to the textbook as possible. The only exception to this rule is that, at the end of this note, we’ll finish by quickly looking at the p-brane action.

2. Relativistic point particle

Explanation of the action for a relativistic point particle as given in Polchinski (eqn. 1.2.2) is best achieved through its first-principle construction. So let us consider the basics of constructing the theory for a relativistic free point particle.

2.1. Minkowski space

We start with a discussion about the space in which we’ll build our theory [Moh08].

As one may recall from studying Einstein’s theory of relativity, spacetime may be modelled by D-dimensional Minkowski space {\mathbb{M}^D} . In the abstract, the basic idea is to consider two (distinct) sets E and {\vec{E}} , where E is a set of points (with no given structure) and {\vec{E}} is a vector space (of free vectors) acting on the set E. We view the elements of {\vec{E}} as forces acting on points in E, which we in turn think of as physical particles. Applying a force (free vector) {X \in \vec{E}} to a point {P \in E} results in a translation. In other words, the action of a force X is to move every point P to the point {P + X \in E} by translation that corresponds to X viewed as a vector.

In physics, the set E is viewed as the D-dimensional affine space {\mathbb{M}^D} , and then {\vec{E}} is the associated D-dimensional vector space {\mathbb{R}^{1,D-1}} defined over the field of real numbers. The choice to model spacetime as an affine space is quite natural, given that an affine space has no preferred or distinguished origin and, of course, the spacetime of special relativity possesses no preferred origin.

As the vectors {X \in \mathbb{R}^{1,D-1}} do not naturally correspond to points {P \in \mathbb{M}} , but rather as displacements relating a point P to another point Q, we write {X = \vec{PQ}} . The points can be defined to be in one-to-one correspondence with a position vector such that {\vec{X}_P = \vec{OP}} , with displacements then defined by the difference {\vec{PQ} = \vec{OQ} - \vec{OP}} . The associated vector space possesses a zero vector {\vec{0} \in \mathbb{R}^{1,D-1}} , which represents the neutral element of vector addition. We can also use the vector space {\mathbb{R}^{1,D-1}} to introduce linear coordinates on {\mathbb{M}^{D}} by making an arbitrary choice of origin as the point {O \in \mathbb{M}^D} .

The elements or points {P,Q,..., \in \mathbb{M}^D} are events, and they combine a moment of time with a specified position. With the arbitrary choice of origin made, we can refer to these points in Minkowski space in terms of their position vectors such that the components {X^{\mu} = (X^0, X^i) = (t, \vec{X})} , with {\mu = 0,..., D-1, i = 1,...,D-1} of vectors {X \in \mathbb{R}^{1,D-1}} correspond to linear coordinates on {\mathbb{M}^D} . The coordinates {X^{0}} is related to the time t, which is measured by an inertial or free falling observer by {X^0 =ct} , with the c the fundamental velocity. The {X^i} coordinates, which are combined into a (D-1)-component vector, parameterise space (from the perspective of the inertial observer).

It is notable that a vector {X} has contravariant coordinates {X^{\mu}} and covariant coordinates {X_{\mu}} which are related by raising and lowering indices such that {X_{\mu} = \eta_{\mu \nu}X^{\nu}} and {X^{\mu} = \eta^{\mu \nu}x_{\nu}} .

We still need to equip a Lorentzian scalar product. In the spacetime of special relativity, the vector space {\mathbb{R}} is furnished with the scalar product (relativistic distance between events)

\displaystyle  \eta_{\mu \nu} = X^{\mu}X_{\mu} = -t^2 + \vec{X}^2 \begin{cases} <0 \ \text{for timelike disrance} \\ =0 \ \text{for lightlike distance} \\ >0 \ \text{for spacelike distance} \end{cases} \ \ (1)

with matrix

\displaystyle  \eta = (\eta_{\mu \nu}) = \begin{pmatrix} - 1 & 0 \\  0 & 1_{D-1} \end{pmatrix}, \ \ (2)

where we have chosen the mostly plus convention. To make sense of (1), since the Minkowski metric (2) is defined by an indefinite scalar product, the distance-squared between events can be positive, zero or negative. This carries information about the causal structure of spacetime. If {X = \vec{PQ}} is the displacement between two events, then these events are called time-like, light-like or space-like relative to each other, depending on X. The zeroth component of X then carries information about the time of the event P as related to Q relative to a given Lorentz frame: P is after Q ({X^0 > Q} ), or simultaneous with Q ({X^0 = 0} ), or earlier than Q ({X^0 < 0} ).

2.2. Lorentz invariance and the Poincaré group

Let’s talk more about Lorentz invariance and the Poincaré group. As inertial observers are required to use linear coordinates which are orthonormal with respect to the scalar product (1), these orthonormal coordinates are distinguished by the above standard form of the metric. It is of course possible to use other curvilinear coordinate systems, such as spherical or cylindrical coordinates. Given the standard form of the metric (2), the most general class of transformations which preserve its form are the Poincaré group, which represents the group of Minkowski spacetime isometries.

The Poincaré group is a 10-dimensional Lie group. It consists of 4 translations along with the Lorentz group of 3 rotations and 3 boosts. As a general review, let’s start with the Lorentz group. This is the set of linear transformations of spacetime that leave the Lorentz interval unchanged.

From the definitions in the previous section, the line element takes the form

\displaystyle  ds^2 = \eta_{\mu \nu}dX^{\mu}dX^{\nu} = - dt^2 + d\vec{X}^2. \ \ (3)

For spacetime coordinates defined in the previous section, the Lorentz group is then defined to be the group of transformations {X^{\mu} \rightarrow X^{\prime \mu}} leaving the relativistic interval invariant. Assuming linearity (we will not prove linearity here, with many proofs easily accessible), define a Lorentz transformation as any real linear transformation {\Lambda} such that

\displaystyle  X^{\mu} \rightarrow X^{\prime \mu} = \Lambda^{\mu}_{\nu}X^{\nu} \ \ (4)

with

\displaystyle  \eta_{\mu \nu} dX^{\prime \mu} dX^{\prime \nu} = \eta_{\mu \nu} dX^{ \mu} dX^{\nu}, \ \ (5)

ensuring from (1) that

\displaystyle  X^{\prime 2} = X^{2}, \ \ (6)

which, for arbitrary X, requires

\displaystyle  \eta_{\mu \nu} = \eta_{\alpha \beta} \Lambda^{\alpha}_{\mu} \Lambda^{\beta}_{\nu}. \ \ (7)

Note that {\Lambda = (\Lambda^{\mu}_{\nu})} is an invertible {D \times D} matrix. In matrix notation (7) can be expressed as

\displaystyle  \Lambda^T \eta \Lambda = \eta. \ \ (8)

Matrices satisfying (8) contain rotations together with Lorentz boosts, which relate inertial frames travelling a constant velocity relative to each other. The Lorentz transformations form a six-dimensional Lie group, which is the Lorentz group O(1,D-1).

For elements {\Lambda \in O(1, D-1)} taking the determinant of (8) gives

\displaystyle  (\det \Lambda)^2 = 1 \implies \det \Lambda = \pm 1. \ \ (9)

By considering the {\Lambda^0_0} component we also find

\displaystyle  (\Lambda^0_0)^2 = 1 + \Sigma_i (\Lambda^0_i)^2 \geq 1 \Rightarrow \Lambda^0_0 \geq 1 \ \text{or} \ \Lambda^0_0 \leq -1. \ \ (10)

So, the Lorentz group has four components according to the signs of {\det \Lambda} and {\Lambda^0_0} . The matrices with {\det \Lambda = 1} form a subgroup SO(1,D-1) with two connected components as given on the right-hand side of (10). The component containing the unit matrix {1 \in O(1,D-1)} is connected and as {SO_0(1,D-1)} .

We may also briefly consider translations of the form

\displaystyle  X^{\mu} \rightarrow X^{\prime \mu} = X^{\mu} + a^{\mu}, \ \ (11)

where {a = (a^{\mu}) \in \mathbb{R}^{1, D-1}} . Translations form a group that can be parametrised by the components of the translation vector {a^{\mu}} .

As mentioned, the Poincaré group is then the complete spacetime symmetry group that combines translations with Lorentz transformations. For a Lorentz transformation {\Lambda} and a translation {a} the combined transformation {(\Lambda, a)} gives

\displaystyle X^{\mu} \rightarrow X^{\prime \mu} = \Lambda^{\mu}_{\nu} X^{\nu} + a^{\mu}. \ \ (12)

These combined transformations form a group since

\displaystyle (\Lambda_2, a_2)(\Lambda_1, a_1) = (\Lambda_2 \Lambda_2, \Lambda_2 a_1 + a_2), \ (\Lambda, a)^{-1} = (\Lambda^{-1}, -\Lambda^{-1}a). \ \ (13)

Since Lorentz transformations and translations do not commute, the Poincaré group is not a direct product. More precisely, the Poincaré group is the semi-direct product of the Lorentz and translation group, {IO(1,D-1) = O(1,D-1) \propto \mathbb{R}^D} .

2.3. Action principle

We now look to construct an action for the relativistic point particle (initially following the discussion in [Zwie09] as motivation).

The classical motion of a point particle as it propagates through spacetime is described by a geodesic on the spacetime. As Polchinski first notes, we can of course describe the motion of this particle by giving its position in terms of functions of time {X(t) = (X^{\mu}(t)) = (t, \vec{X}(t))} . For now, we may also consider some arbitrary origin and endpoint {(ct_f, \vec{X}_{f})} for the particle’s path or what is also called its worldline. We also know from the principle of least action that there are many possible paths between these points.

Particle worldline

It should be true that for any worldline all Lorentz observers compute the same value for the action. Let {\mathcal{P}} denote one such worldline. Then we may use the proper time as an Lorentz invariant quantity to describe this path. Moreover, from special relativity one may recall that the proper time is a Lorentz invariant measure of time. If different Lorentz observers will record different values for the time interval between the two events along {\mathcal{P}} , then we instead imagine that attached to the particle is a clock. The proper time is therefore the time elapsed between the two events on that clock, according to which all Lorentz observers must agree on the amount of elapsed time. This is the basic idea, and it means we want an action of the worldline {\mathcal{P}} that is proportional to the proper time.

To achieve this, we first recall the invariant interval for the motion of a particle

\displaystyle  - ds^2 = -c^2 dt^2 + (dX^1)^2 + (dX^2)^2 + (dX^3)^2, \ \ (14)

in which, from special relativity, the proper time

\displaystyle  -ds^2 = -c^2 dt_f \rightarrow ds = c dt_f \ \ (15)

tells us that for timelike intervals ds/c is the proper time interval. It follows that the integral of (ds/c) over the worldline {\mathcal{P}} gives the proper time elapsed on {\mathcal{P}} . But, if the proper time gives units of time, we still needs units of energy or units of mass times velocity-squared to ensure we have the full units of action (recall that for any dynamical system the action has units of energy times time, with the Lagrangian possessing units of energy). We also need to ensure that we preserve Lorentz invariance in the process of building our theory. One obvious choice is m for the rest mass of the particle, with c for the fundamental velocity in relativity. Then we have an overall multiplicative factor {mc^2} that represents the the rest energy of the particle. As a result, the action takes the tentative form {mc^2 (ds/c) = mc ds} . This should make some sense in that {ds} is just a Lorentz scalar, and we have the factor of relativity we expect. We also include a minus sign to ensure the follow integrand is real for timelike geodesics.

\displaystyle  S = -mc \int_{\mathcal{P}} ds. \ \ (16)

A good strategy now is to find an integral of our Lagrangian over time – say, {t_i} and {t_f} which are world-events that we’ll take to define our interval – because it will enable use to establish a more satisfactory expression that includes the values of time at the initial and final points of our particle’s path. If we fix a frame – which is to say if we choose the frame of a particular Lorentz observer – we may express the action (16) as the integral of the Lagrangian over time. To achieve this end, we must first return to our interval (14) and relate {ds} to {dt} ,

\displaystyle  -ds^2 = -c^2 dt^2 + (dX^1)^2 + (dX^2)^2 + (dX^3)^2

\displaystyle  ds^2 = c^2 dt^2 - (dX^1)^2 - (dX^2)^2 - (dX^3)^2

\displaystyle  ds^2 = [c^2 - \frac{(dX^1)^2}{dt} - \frac{(dX^2)^2}{dt} - \frac{(dX^3)^2}{dt}] dt^2

\displaystyle  \implies ds^2 = (c^2 - v^2) dt^2

\displaystyle  \therefore ds = \sqrt{c^2 - v^2} dt. \ \ (17)

With this relation between {ds} and {dt} , in the fixed frame the point particle action becomes

\displaystyle  S = -mc^{2} \int_{t_{i}}^{t_{f}} dt \sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}, \ \ (18)

with the Lagrangian taking the form

\displaystyle  L = -mc^{2} \sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}. \ \ (19)

This Lagrangian gives us a hint that it is correct as its logic breaks down when the velocity exceeds the speed of light {v > c} . This confirms the definition of the proper time from special relativity (i.e., the velocity should not exceed the speed of light for the proper time to be a valid concept). In the small velocity limit {v << c} , on the other hand, when we expand the square root (just use binomial theorem to approximate) we see that it gives

\displaystyle L \simeq -mc^2 (1 - \frac{1}{2}\frac{v^2}{c^2}) = - mc^2 + \frac{1}{2}m v^2. \ \ (20)

returning similar structure for the kinetic part of the free non-relativistic particle, with ({-mc^2} ) just a constant.

2.4. Canonical momentum and Hamiltonian

We will discuss the canonical momentum of the point particle again in a future note on quantisation; but for the present form of the action it is worth highlighting that we can also see the Lagrangian (19) is correct by computing the momentum {\vec{p}} and the Hamiltonian.

For the canonical momentum, we take the derivative of the Lagrangian with respect to the velocity

\displaystyle  \vec{p} = \frac{\partial L}{\partial \vec{v}} = -mc^{2}(-\frac{\vec{v}}{c^{2}})\frac{1}{\sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}} = \frac{m\vec{v}}{\sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}}. \ \ (21)

Now that we have an expression for the relativistic momentum of the particle, let us consider the Hamiltonian. The Hamiltonian may be written schematically as {H = \vec{p} \cdot \vec{v} - L} . All we need to do is make the appropriate substitutions,

\displaystyle  H = \frac{m\vec{v}^{2}}{\sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}} + mc^{2}\sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}} = \frac{mc^{2}}{\sqrt{1 - \frac{v^{2}}{c^{2}}}}. \ \ (22)

The Hamiltonian should make sense. Notice, if we instead write the result in terms of the particle’s momentum (rather than velocity) by inverting (22), we find an expression in terms of the relativistic energy {\frac{E^{2}}{c^{2}} - \vec{p} \cdot \vec{p} = m^{2}c^{2}} . This is a deep hint that we’re on the right track, as it suggests quite clearly that we’ve recovered basic relativistic physics for a point-like object.

3. Reparameterisation invariance

An important property of the action (16) is that it is invariant under whatever choice of parameterisation we might choose. This makes sense because the invariant length ds between two points on the particle’s worldline does not depend on any parameterisation. We’ve only insisted on integrating the line element, which, if you think about it, is really just a matter of adding up all of the infinitesimal segments along the worldline. But, typically, a particle moving in spacetime is described by a parameterised curve. As Polchinski notes, it is generally best to introduce some parameter and then describe the motion in spacetime by functions of that parameter.

Furthermore, how we parameterise the particle’s path will govern whether, for the classical motion, the path is one that extremises the invariant distance ds as a minimum or maximum. Our choice of {\tau}-parameterisation is such that the invariant length ds is given by

\displaystyle ds^2 = -\eta_{\mu \nu}(X) dX^{\mu} dX^{\nu}, \ \ (23)

then the choice of worldline parameter {\tau} is considered to be increasing between some initial point {X^{\mu} (\tau_i)} and some final point {X^{\mu}(\tau_f)} . So the classical paths are those which maximise the proper time. It also means that the trajectory of the particle worldline is now described by the coordinates {X^{\mu} = X^{\mu}(\tau)} . As a result, the space of the theory can now be updated such that {X^{\mu}(\tau) \in \mathbb{R}^{1, D-1}} with {\mu, \nu = 0,...,D-1} .

In the use of {\tau} parameterisation, an important idea is that time is in a sense being promoted to a dynamical degree of freedom without it actually being a dynamical degree of freedom. We are in many ways leveraging the power of gauge symmetry, with our choice of parameterisation enabling us to treat space and time coordinates on equal footing. The cost by trading a less symmetric description for a more symmetric one is that we pick up redundancies.

Given the previous preference of background spacetime geometry to be Minkowski, recall the metric

\displaystyle  \eta_{\mu \nu} = \begin{pmatrix} -1 & 0 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 1 & 0 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 1 & 0 \\ 0 & 0 & 0 & 1 \end{pmatrix}, \ \ (24)

such that for the integrand ds we now use

\displaystyle -\eta_{\mu \nu}(X) dX^{\mu} dX^{\nu} = -\eta_{\mu \nu}(X) \frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau)}{d\tau} \frac{dX^{\nu}(\tau)}{d\tau} d\tau^2. \ \ (25)

Therefore, the action (16) may be updated to take the form

\displaystyle  S_{pp} = -mc \int_{\tau_i}^{\tau_f} d\tau \ \sqrt{-\eta_{\mu \nu} \dot{X}^{\mu} \dot{X}^{\nu}} \ \ (26)

with {\dot{X}^{\mu} \equiv dX^{\mu}(\tau) / d\tau} .

Setting {c = 1} , notice (26) is precisely the action (eqn. 1.2.2) in Polchinski. This is the simplest action for a relativistic point particle with manifest Poincaré invariance that does not depend on the choice of parameterisation.

How do we interpret this form of the action? In the exercise to obtain (26) we have essentially played the role of a fixed observer, who has calculated the action using some parameter {\tau} . The important question is whether the value of the action depends on this choice of parameter. Polchinski comments that, in fact, it is a completely arbitrary choice of parameterisation. This should make sense because, again, the invariant length ds on the particle worldline {\mathcal{P}} should not depend on how the path is parameterised.

Proposition 1 The action (26) is reparameterisation invariant such that if we replace {\tau} with the parameter {\tau^{\prime} = f(\tau)} , where f is monotonic, we obtain the same value for the action.

Proof: Consider the following reparameterisation of the particle’s worldline {\tau \rightarrow \tau^{\prime} = f(\tau)} . Then we have

\displaystyle d\tau \rightarrow d\tau^{\prime} = \frac{\partial f}{\partial \tau}d\tau, \ \ (27)

implying

\displaystyle  \frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau^{\prime})}{d\tau} = \frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau^{\prime})}{d\tau^{\prime}}\frac{d\tau^{\prime}}{d\tau} = \frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau^{\prime})}{d\tau^{\prime}} \frac{\partial f(\tau)}{\partial \tau}. \ \ (28)

Plugging this into the action (26) we get

\displaystyle S^{\prime} = -mc \int_{\tau_i}^{\tau_f} d\tau^{\prime} \ \sqrt{\frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau^{\prime})}{d\tau^{\prime}} \frac{dX_{\mu}(\tau^{\prime})}{d\tau^{\prime}}}

\displaystyle  = -mc \int_{\tau_i}^{\tau_f} \frac{\partial f}{\partial \tau} \ d\tau \ \sqrt{\frac{dX^{\mu}}{d\tau} \frac{dX_{\mu}}{d\tau} (\frac{\partial f}{\partial tau})^{-2}}

\displaystyle  = -mc \int_{\tau_i}^{\tau_f} (\frac{\partial f}{\partial \tau})(\frac{\partial f}{\partial \tau})^{-1} \ d\tau \ \sqrt{\frac{dX^{\mu}}{d\tau} \frac{dX_{\mu}}{d\tau}}

\displaystyle  = -mc \int_{\tau_i}^{\tau_f} d\tau \ \sqrt{\frac{dX^{\mu}(\tau)}{d\tau} \frac{dX_{\mu}(\tau)}{d\tau}}. \ \ (29)

\Box

This ends the proof. So we see the value of the action does not depend on the choice of parameter; indeed, the choice is arbitrary.

As alluded earlier in this section, reparameterisation invariance is a gauge symmetry. In some sense, this is not even an honest symmetry; because it means that we’ve introduced a redundancy in our description, as not all degrees of freedom {X^{\mu}} are physically meaningful. We’ll discuss this more in the context of the string (an example of such a redundancy appears in the study of the momenta).

4. Equation of motion for {S_{pp}}

To obtain (eqn. 1.2.3), Polchinski varies the action (26) and then integrates by parts. For simplicity, let us temporarily maintain {c = 1} . Varying (26)

\displaystyle  \delta S_{pp} = -m \int d\tau \delta (\sqrt{-\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}_{\mu}}) \ \ (30)

\displaystyle  = -m \int d\tau \frac{1}{2}(-\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}_{\mu})^{-1/2}(-\delta \dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}_{\mu}), \ \ (31)

then from the last term we pick up a factor of 2 leaving

\displaystyle  = -m \int d\tau (-\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}_{\mu})^{-1/2} + (-\dot{X}^{\mu}\delta \dot{X}_{\mu}). \ \ (32)

Next, we make the substitution {u^{\mu} = \dot{X}^{\mu}(-\dot{X}^{\nu}\dot{X}_{\nu})^{-1/2}} such that

\displaystyle  \delta S_{pp} = -m \int d\tau (-u_{\mu})\delta \dot{X}^{\mu}. \ \ (33)

And now we integrate by parts, which shifts a derivative onto u using the fact we can commute the variation and the derivative {\delta \dot{X}^{\mu} = \delta d / d\tau X^{\mu} = d/d\tau \delta X^{\mu}} . We also drop the total derivative term that we obtain in the process

\displaystyle  \delta S_{pp} = -m \int d\tau \frac{d}{d\tau} (-u_{\mu}\delta X^{\mu}) - m \int d\tau \dot{u}_{\mu} \delta X^{\mu}, \ \ (34)

which gives the correct result

\displaystyle  \delta S_{pp} = -m \int d\tau \dot{u}_{\mu}\delta X^{\mu}. \ \ (34)

As Polchinski notes, the equation of motion {\dot{u}^{\mu} = 0} describes the free motion of the particle.

With the particle mass m being the normalisation constant, we can also take the non-relativistic limit to find (exercise 1.1). Returning to (26), one way to do this is for {\tau} to be the proper time, then, as before (reinstating c for the purpose of example)

\displaystyle  \dot{X}^{\mu}(\tau) = c \frac{dt}{d\tau} + \frac{d\vec{X}^{\mu}(\tau)}{d\tau} \ \ (35)

so that we may define the quantity {\gamma = (1 - v^2/c^2)^{-1/2}} . Then, in the non-relativistic limit where {v << c} we have {dt/d\tau = \gamma = 1 + \mathcal{O}(v^2/c^2)} . It follows

\displaystyle  \dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}_{\mu} = -c^2 + \mid \vec{v} \mid^2 + \mathcal{O}(v^2/c^2), \ \ (36)

with {\vec{v}} a spatial vector and we define the norm {\mid \vec{v} \mid \equiv v} . Now, equivalent as with the choice of static gauge, the action to order {v/c} takes the form

\displaystyle S_{pp} \approx -mc \int dt \sqrt{c^2 -\mid \vec{v} \mid^2}, \ \ (37)

where we now taylor expand to give

\displaystyle  S_{pp} \approx -mc \int (1 - \frac{1}{2}\frac{\mid \vec{v} \mid^2}{c^2}) \ \ (38)

Observe that we now have a time integral of a term with classical kinetic structure minus a potential-like term (actually a total time derivative) that is an artefact of the relative rest energy

\displaystyle  S_{pp} \approx \int dt \ (\frac{1}{2}m\mid \vec{v} \mid^2 - mc^2). \ \ (39)

5. Deriving {S_{pp}^{\prime}} (eqn. 1.2.5)

The main problem with the action (18) and equivalently (26) is that, when we go to quantise this theory, the square root function in the integrand is non-linear. Analogously, we will find a similar issue upon constructing the first-principle string action, namely the Nambu-Goto action. Additionally, in our study of the bosonic string, we will be interested firstly in studying massless particles. But notice that according to the action (26) a massless particle would be zero.

What we want to do is rewrite {S_{PP}} in yet another equivalent form. To do this, we add an auxiliary field so that our new action takes the form

\displaystyle  S_{pp}^{\prime} = \frac{1}{2} \int d \tau (\eta^{-1} \dot{X}^{\mu} \dot{X}_{\mu} - \eta m^2), \ \ (40)

where we define the tetrad {\eta (\tau) = (- \gamma_{\tau \tau} (\tau))^{\frac{1}{2}}} . The independent worldline metric {\gamma_{\tau \tau}(\tau)} that we’ve introduce as an additional field is, in a sense, a generalised Lagrange multiplier. For simplicity we can denote this additional field {e(\tau)} so that we get the action

\displaystyle  S_{pp}^{\prime} = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau (e^{-1} \dot{X}^{2} - em^{2}), \ \ (41)

where we have simplified the notation by setting {\dot{X}^{2} = \eta_{\mu \nu}\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu}} and completely eliminated the square root. This is equivlant to what Polchinski writes in (eqn.1.2.5). The structure of (41) may look familiar, as it reads like a worldline theory coupled to 1-dimensional gravity (worth checking and playing with).

To see that {S_{pp}^{\prime}} is classically equivalent (on-shell) to {S_{pp}} , we first consider its variation with respect to {e(\tau)}

\displaystyle  \delta S_{pp}^{\prime} = \frac{1}{2}\delta \int d\tau (e^{-1} \dot{X}^{2} - m^2 e)

\displaystyle  = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau (- \delta (\frac{1}{e})\dot{X}^{2} - \delta (m^{2} e))

\displaystyle  = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau (- \frac{1}{e^{2}}\dot{X}^{2} - m^{2}), \ \ (42)

which results in the following field equations

\displaystyle  e^{2} = \frac{\dot{X}^{2}}{m^{2}}

\displaystyle  \implies e = \sqrt{\frac{-\dot{X}^{2}}{m^{2}}} \ \ (43).

This again aligns with Polchinski’s result (eqn. 1.2.7).

Proposition 2 If we substitute (43) back into (41), we recover the original {S_{pp}} action (26).

Proof:

\displaystyle  S_{pp}^{\prime} = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau [(-\frac{\dot{X}^2}{m^{2}})^{-1/2} \dot{X}^{2} - m^{2}(-\frac{\dot{X}^{2}}{m^{2}})^{1/2}]

\displaystyle  = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau [(-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} (\dot{X}^{2} - m^{2}(\frac{\dot{X}^{2}}{m^{2}})^{1/2})]

\displaystyle  = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau [(-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} (\dot{X}^{2} - m (- \dot{X}^{2})^{1/2})] \ \ (44)

Recalling {\dot{X}^{2} = \eta_{\mu \nu} \dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu}} , substitute for {\dot{X}} in the square root on the right-hand side

\displaystyle  = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau [(-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} \dot{X}^{2} - m (- \eta_{\mu \nu} \dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu})^{1/2}. \ \ (45)

For the first term we clean up with a bit of algebra. From complex variables recall {i^{2} = -1} .

\displaystyle  (-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} \dot{X}^{2} = (-1)(-1) -(\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} \dot{X}^{2}

\displaystyle  = -(-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}})^{1/2} i^{2} \dot{X}^{2}

\displaystyle = -(-\frac{m^{2}}{\dot{X}^{2}} i^{4} \dot{X}^{2})^{1/2}

\displaystyle  = -(-m^{2}i^{4}\dot{X}^{2})^{1/2} = -m (-i^{4}\dot{X}^{2})^{1/2}. \ \ (46)

As {i^{4} = 1} , it follows {-m(i^{4}\dot{X}^{2})^{1/2} = -m (-\dot{X}^{2})^{1/2}} . Now, substitute for {\dot{X}^{2}} and we find {-m (-\eta_{\mu \nu}\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu})^{1/2}} giving

\displaystyle  S_{pp}^{\prime} = \frac{1}{2} \int d\tau [-m(- \eta_{\mu \nu}\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu})^{1/2} - m (- \eta_{\mu \nu} \dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu})^{1/2}

\displaystyle  = -m \int d\tau (- \eta_{\mu \nu}\dot{X}^{\mu}\dot{X}^{\nu})^{1/2} = S_{pp} \ \ (47).

\Box

This ends the proof, demonstrating that {S_{pp}} and {S_{pp}^{\prime}} are classically equivalent.

It is also possible to show that, like with {S_{pp}} , the action {S_{pp}^{\prime}} is both Poincaré invariant and reparameterisation invariant.

6. Generalising to Dp-branes

As an aside, and to conclude this note, we can generalise the action for a point particle (0-brane) to an action for a p-brane. It follows that a p-brane in a {D \geq p} dimensional background spacetime can be described in such a way that the action becomes,

\displaystyle  S_{pb}= -T_p \int d\mu_p \ \ (48).

The term {T_p} is one that will become more familiar moving forward, especially when we begin to discuss the concept of string tension. However, in the above action it denotes the p-brane tension, which has units of mass/volume. The {d\mu_p} term is the {(p + 1)} -dimensional volume measure,

\displaystyle  d\mu_p = \sqrt{- \det G_{ab}} \ d^{p+1} \sigma, \ \ (49)

where {G_{ab}} is the induced metric, which, in the {p = 1} case, we will understand as the worldsheet metric. The induce metric is given by,

\displaystyle  G_{ab} (X) = \frac{\partial X^{\mu}}{\partial \sigma^{a}} \frac{\partial X^{\nu}}{\partial \sigma^{b}} h_{\mu \nu}(X) \ \ \ a, b \equiv 0, 1, ..., p \ \ (50)  p>

A few additional comments may follow. As {\sigma^{0} \equiv \tau} , spacelike coordinates in this theory run as {\sigma^{1}, \sigma^{2}, ... \sigma^{p}} for the surface traced out by the p-brane. Under {\tau} reparameterisation, the above action may also be shown to be invariant.

7. Summary

To summarise, one may recall how in classical (non-relativistic) theory [LINK] the evolution of a system is described by its field equations. One can generalise many of the concepts of the classical non-relativistic theory of a point particle to the case of the relativistic point particle. Indeed, one will likely be familiar with how in the non-relativistic case the path of the particle may be characterised as a path through space. This path is then parameterised by time. On the other hand, in the case of the relativistic point particle, we have briefly reviewed how the path may instead be characterised by a worldline through spacetime. This worldline is parameterised not by time, but by the proper time. And, in relativity, we learn in very succinct terms how freely falling relativistic particles move along geodesics.

It should be understood that the equations of motion for the relativistic point particle are given by the geodesics on the spacetime. This means that one must remain cognisant that whichever path the particle takes also has many possibilities, as noted in an earlier section. That is, there are many possible worldlines between some beginning point and end point. This useful fact will be explicated more thoroughly later on, where, in the case of the string, we will discuss the requirement to sum over all possible worldsheets. Other lessons related to the point particle will also be extended to the string, and will help guide how we construct the elementary string action.

References

[Moh08] T. Mohaupt, Liverpool lectures on string theory [lecture notes].

[Pol07] J. Polchinski, An introduction to the bosonic string. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. (2007).

[Wray11] K. Wray, An introduction to string theory [lecture notes].

[Zwie09] B. Zwiebach, A first course in string theory. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. (2009).

(n-1)-thoughts, n=4: Covid, Twitter news, and Douglas Adams

Covid days

This is my first post in some weeks. Admittedly, I am one that can easily lose track of time as I get absorbed in one calculation or another. But that is not the reason for my lack of writing.

It was my turn to experience Covid for the first time. For the first 7-10 days, it hit me quite hard relatively speaking as being a person who is vaccinated. The second week I mostly struggled with a persistent dry cough, fatigue, and weakness. I remember reading at the height of the pandemic people with Covid saying that it felt like ‘being hit by bus’. I struggle to understand what this actually meant, because I imagine being hit by a bus to be a rather gruesome event. But, in the peak of my own Covid days, I think I finally realised the true meaning of the words.

Thankfully, I am feeling better now. Although super busy catching up with work and developing some new calculations for potential papers, I look forward to getting back to posting on my blog. When I don’t write for a while, it starts to impact my mental health. It’s just something that I greatly enjoy. It helps me process, sometimes even indirectly, and can even help stimulate news thoughts, much the same with reading a good book. There are some very nice physics papers that I would like to write about. One in particular offers what I thought was a rather astounding result. So I’ll probably start there, and then also continue uploading my old string notes based on Polchinski’s textbooks.

Twitter news

I prefer a world where Twitter is not so important. Don’t get me wrong, I enjoy Twitter. It has some fantastic communities. When I use the app, it’s primarily to check for fun maths posts, science news, history papers, or cool new archaeological finds. I also enjoy some of the technical F1 discussions, or the odd bit of literary discussion. When it works – that is, when my feed is adequately filtered so that I don’t have to skim through pages minutiae, such as when people feel the urge to share every passing thought or post what they had for lunch – I find that Twitter can be an enjoyable and certainly also positive experience.

Granted, my experience is limited and intentionally curated: I tend to keep to small communities in which discussion is generally reasonable, where the flow of information is well-assessed and knowledgeable. Sometimes there is constructive debate, sometimes deep disagreement, and other times challenging questions are asked or interesting perspectives offered. I’ve found that Twitter can also provide opportunities to interact positively with others in ways that may have not been otherwise possible. For instance, Steve Brusatte, a very well-known palaeontologist, wrote to me to say that he hopes I enjoy his book. (The book was fantastic, by the way). I thought that was awesome. I also enjoy interactions with other scientists, reading about what they are working on; and, during the pandemic, it allowed me to follow some leading virologists and epidemiologists – including some at my university – to track the latest studies and policy discussions.

Twitter may not be worth $44bn for these reasons – I imagine instead it is because of its power to decide elections that makes it so valuable to the right people – but, at least for me, it is within such a limited context that I’ve found it useful and at times a valuable information feed.

But I also know that Twitter can be a cesspool. I am keenly aware that it faces many problems and challenges. The way in which the social media platform is structured seems to often nullify the very goal it was supposed to realise, assuming a priori the goal was social and democratic in the first place. In much of the literature, introductions to social media ecologies often speak praisingly about the promise of social media without addressing critically its many obvious social and political complexities. Managing the preservation of free speech, combating hate speech, ensuring inclusivity, and encouraging greater representation (to name a few) are all hot-topic issues. As an extension of the social world, the platform is also plagued by toxicity, the constant drone of stupidity, identity politics, inconsequential opinionizing, and petty bickering.

(The last I saw, only 15-20% of the UK population use Twitter, and it is reasonable to think that the amount of people that actively post and engage on the platform is much smaller. I think it is comparably similar in the US. So, perhaps one explanation is that, at least in general, it is much more an abode for extremists and activists will to battle over their ideological worldview than an honest reflection of the average citizen. I’m not entirely sure).

One of the fundamental problems with Twitter, and really social media in general, is its lack of accountability. There is a fine line between banning users without reasonable explanation and justification – or banning users because of political speech that may not be deemed agreeable according to whatever metric – and banning users whose speech incites violence or hate. I’m sure most readers of this blog would agree that speech that incites violence is unacceptable. But what about speech that – whether in bad faith, out of ignorance, or otherwise – spreads misinformation? We live in what is generally a post-fact, post-truth society; communicative reason, or its absence, within this context is where misinformation for one group is what another group believes. What people think is true is much more important and meaningful than what is actually true. Hence, the polarisation of political viewpoints and attitudes – the underlying trend that gives authority to ideology over objective methodology – is legitimated in so many different ways.

As the Twitter continues to grow increasingly powerful, the lack of accountability becomes increasingly magnified. I am not just speaking of bans due to political speech, which I think is quite troubling (even when I might not agree with that speech); the subtlties between information and misinformation; issues with corporate agents and social media influencers, who are invested in propagating a certain message or viewpoint to sell their products; or the way in which powerful people with investment in certain political and economic outcomes may use the platform to shape important historical events (however honestly or dishonestly). I think what is perhaps most troubling is that Twitter, as a social ecosystem in itself, has become an echo chamber for groups that, instead of promoting healthy engagement, strengthens the legitimisation of communication driven toward confirmation bias and cognitive prejudice.

Social bias and prejudice, as rampant as it is actively enabled, generally forms a massive part of what shapes people’s opinions and political viewpoints today. Perhaps it has always been this way. But in the digital world, paradoxically, the manifestation of a type of behaviour that seeks only information that reinforces opinion – certainly an artifact of a deeply human impulse – seems to easily become extremised. One manifestation of this is of course the ‘click bait’ phenomenon. ‘The headline confirms what I think’, and then move on. But even in the best case toy example in which two rational actors may be discussing a topic in a mutually encircling way, social media platforms like Twitter function on the basis of the reduction of information to mere snippets and at the cost of substantive analysis. In opinion, it is not the abundance of thought that is the problem in our historical present; it is the lack of slow, substantive and meaningful thought that ails us. Twitter is the perfect example.

We can extend the discussion down more philosophical paths and also consider the way in which this has impacted the role that “facts” and “truth” (and their absence) play in a society increasingly lacking in its support of rational faculty. If people weren’t so easily influenced by everything they read, then maybe the problem of social media and its symplistic information streams (i.e., read a meme and decide it’s representative of one’s worldview) would be mitagated to some degree. There is a reason why current and past US Presidents, and likewise why current and past British Primeministers, speak at the level of GSCE english (or lower) when delivering public speeches. But, given the emerging patterns of simplistic information streams and what drives this emergence (which is certainly a complicated array of forces, including increasing public demands for transparency), the prevailing trend is one of reductionist and equally ideologically-form-fitting narratives (typically confirmation bias consumed with greatest ease and with least friction against one’s established worldview).

This brings me to the news this week that Elon Musk has bought Twitter. Inasmuch the news sparked anger and consternation on one side, there is another group that has celebrated the announcement, entrusting Musk the responsibility to manage accountability. He is, afterall, a self-proclaimed ‘free speech absolutist’ (for consistancy sake, let’s ignore the obvious contradictions in behaviour). It’s like any of the buzzwords that characterise the strange identity wars going on. The concepts are largely dumbed down on either side so that everyone has an opinion, made accessible in such a way that the framing of issues require no expertise or well-defined knowledge. Going back to Musk, in my opinion, it is a fool’s game to be absolutist in anything; but the sentiment obviously sticks in a time when freedom of speech is percieved by many to be under threat. And yet, as Twitter has taught me, hyperbole about one’s principles can easily become an idiot’s fable.

I have a hard time believing that, under Musk’s ownership, anything fundamental with Twitter will change. If he indeed percieves Twitter as the online town hall where people can debate important issues, then I suppose what’s left is to lament the loss of the principle of debate; because Twitter is certainly not the venue. It’s like, with so much energised attention on freedom of speech within social media ecologies, where a person may without thought say anything, we are quick to preserve the sacred right that a human being is completely entitled to an opinion without evidence and then just as fast forget that as soon as such an opinion is expressed as fact it becomes a lie. Indeed, in my most pessimistic moments I would say that social media, in helping manifest the much deeper separation of reason from social discourse, has eagrly retained the idea of free speech at the loss of the rationality that makes it meaningful in the first place.

A quote by Douglas Adams

The major problem—one of the major problems, for there are several—one of the many major problems with governing people is that of whom you get to do it; or rather of who manages to get people to let them do it to them.

To summarize: it is a well-known fact that those people who must want to rule people are, ipso facto, those least suited to do it.

To summarize the summary: anyone who is capable of getting themselves made President should on no account be allowed to do the job.

– Douglas Adams

Learning M-theory: Gauge theory of membranes, brane intersections, and the self-dual string

I’ve been learning a lot about M-theory. It’s such a broad topic that, when people ask me ‘what is M-theory?’, I continue to struggle to know where to start. Right now, much of my learning is textbook and I have more questions than answers. I naturally take the approach of first wanting as broad and general of a picture as possible. In some sense, it is like starting with the general and working toward the particular. Or, in another way, it’s like when being introduced to a new landscape and wanting, at the outset, a broad orientation to its general geographical features, except in this case we are speaking in conceptual and quantitative terms. I may not ever be smart enough to grasp M-theory in its entirety, but what is certain is that I am working my hardest.

In surveying its geographical features and charting my own map, if I may continue the analogy, obtaining a better sense of the fundamental objects of M-theory is a particular task; but my main research interest has increasingly narrowed to the study and application of gauge theory and higher gauge theory. This can be sliced down further in that I am very interested in the relationship between string and gauge theory, and furthermore in studying the higher dimensional generalisation of gauge theory. This interest naturally follows from the importance of gauge theory in contemporary physics, and then how we may understand it from the generalisation of point particle theory to string theory and then to other higher dimensional extended objects (i.e., branes). We’ve talked a bit in the past about how the dynamics on the D-brane worldvolume is described by a gauge theory. We’ve also touched on categorical descriptions, and how in p-brane language when we study the quantum theory the resemblance of the photon can be seen as a p-dimensional version of the electromagnetic field (by the way, we’re going to start talking about p-branes in my next string note). That is to say, we obtain a p-dimensional analogue of Maxwell’s equations. More advanced perspectives from the gauge theory view, or in this case higher gauge theory view in M-theory, illuminate the existence of new objects like self-dual strings.

There is so much here to write about and explore, I look forward to sharing more as I progress through my own studies and thinking. In this post, though, I want to share some notebook reflections on things I’ve been learning more generally in the context of M-theory: some stuff about membranes, 11-dimensional supergravity, and the self-dual string. This post is not very technical; it’s just me thinking out loud.

11-dimensional supergravity

The field content of 11-dimensional supergravity consists of the metric g_{\mu \nu}  , with 44 degrees of freedom; a rank 3 anti-symmetric tensor field C_{\mu \nu \rho}  , with 84 degrees of freedom; and these are paired off with a 32 component Majorana gravitino \Psi_{\alpha \mu}  , with 128 degrees of freedom. Although much has progressed since originally conceived, the Lagrangian for the bosonic sector is similar to as it was originally written [3]

S_{SUGRA} = \frac{1}{2k_{11}^2} \int_{M_{11}} \sqrt{g} \ (R - \frac{1}{48}F^{2}_{4}) - \frac{1}{6} F_{4} \wedge F_{4} \wedge C_3. \ \ (1)

The field strength is F_4 = dC_3  and k_{11}  is the 11-dimensional coupling constant. The field strength is defined conventionally,

\mid F_n \mid^2 = \frac{1}{n !} G^{M_1 N_1} G^{M_2 N_2} ... G^{M_n N_n}F_{M_{1}M_{2} ... M_{n}}F_{N_1 N_2 ... N_n}. \ \ (2)

The 11-dimensional frame field in the metric combination is G_{MN} = \eta_{AB}E^{A}_{M}E^{B}_{N}  , where we have the elfbeins E^{B}_{N}  , M,N  are indices for curved base-space vectors, and A,B  are indices for tangent space vectors. The last term in (2) is the Cherns-Simons structure. This is a topological dependent term independent of the metric. We see this structure in a lot of different contexts.

Although, from what I presently understand, the total degrees of freedom of M-theory are not yet completely nailed down, we can of course begin to trace a picture in parameter space. As we’ve discussed before on this blog, it can be seen how 10-dimensional type IIA theory in the strong coupling regime behaves as an 11-dimensional theory whose low-energy limit is captured by 11-dimensional supergravity. Reversely, compactify 11-dimensional supergravity on a circle of fixed radius in the x^{10} = z  direction, from the 11-dimensional metric we then obtain the 10-dimensional metric, a vector field and the dilaton. The 3-form potential leads to both a 3-form and a 2-form in 10-dimensions. The mysterious 11-dimensional theory can also be seen to give further clue at its parental status given how supergravity compactified on unit interval {\mathbb{I} = [0,1]}  , for example, leads to the low-energy limit of E8 \times E8  heterotic theory.

Non-renomoralisability of 11-dimensional SUGRA

One thing that I’ve known about for sometime but I have not yet studied in significant detail concerns precisely how 11-dimensional supergravity is non-renormalisable [4,5,6]. Looking at the maths, what I understand is that above two-loops the graviton-graviton scattering is divergent. Moreover, as I still have some questions about this, what I find curious is that in the derivative expansion in 11-dimensional flat spacetime (using a 1PI/quantum effective Lagrangian approach) the generating functional for the graviton S-matrix is non-local. But due to supersymmetry, low order terms in the derivative expansion can be separated into local terms, such as t_8 t_8 R^4  , and non-local (or global) terms that correspond to loop amplitudes. But what happens is that, at 2-loops, a logarithmic divergence that is cut off at the Planck scale mixes with a local term of the schematic form D^{12}R^4  , where R^4  is the supersymmetrised vertex. In the literature, one will find a lot of discussion about this R^4  vertex. But like I said, I really need more time looking at this.

In short, the important mechanism in string theory that allows us to avoid UV divergences is absent, or appears absent, in maximal supergravity. What could the UV regulator be? As in any supergravity, from what I understand, it is not clear that a Lagrangian description is sufficient at the Planck scale.

Membranes, D-branes, and AdS/CFT

The facts of 11-dimensional supergravity and how it relates to 10-dimensional string theory are textbook and well-known. Going beyond dualities relating different string theories, an obvious question concerns what M-theory actually constitutes. One thing that is known is that M-theory reduces to 11-dimensional SUGRA at low-energies, as we touched on, and it is known that fundamental degrees of freedom are 2-dimensional and 5-dimensional objects, known as M2-branes and M5-branes. Study of these non-perturbative states offer several intriguing hints. There are also solutions to classical supergravity known as F1 – the fundamental string – and its magnetic dual, the NS5-brane. As it relates to the story of the five string theories, the M-branes realize all D-branes, and this is why D-branes are considered consistent objects in quantum gravity.

The way that M-theory sees D-branes is via the net of dualities. All of the D-branes and the NS5 brane are solutions to type II theories, both A and B. So, when you reduce M-theory on a circle, in that you get back to Type IIA, the M2-branes and M5-branes reduce to the various D-branes such that under S-duality from the D5-brane you get the NS5.

The worldvolume theory of the M5-brane is always strongly coupled, which can be seen in moduli space (its parameters are simply a point). So there is no Lagrangian for this theory, and it suggests something deep is needed or is missing. It is expected that its worldvolume theory will be a 6-dimensional superconformal field theory, typically known as the 6d(2,0) theory. The worldvolume theory for M2-branes (on an orbifold) has been found to be a 3-dimensional superconformal Chern-Simons theory with classical \mathcal{N} = 6 supersymmetry.

If one considers a single M5-brane, a theory can be formulated in terms of an Abelian (2,0)-tensor multiplet, consisting of a self-dual 2-form gauge field, 5 scalars, and 8 fermions, but it is not known how to generalise the construction to describe multiple M5-branes. To give an example, using AdS/CFT [7] it is described how the worldvolume theory for a stack of N  M5-branes is dual to M-theory on AdS7 \times S4  with N  units of flux through the 4-sphere, which reduces to 11-dimensional SUGRA on this background in the limit large N  limit.

Brane intersections and stacks

The existence of branes is one of the most fascinating things about quantum gravity. There is a lot to unpack when learning about D1-branes, D3-branes, D5-branes, M2-branes, and M5-branes, as well as how they may intersect and what sort of consistent solutions have already been found [8,9, 10, 11, 12].

For example, an M2-brane, or a stack of coincident M2-branes, can end on a D5-brane. This is similar to the more simplified story of how D-branes, coincident D-branes, can intersect in string theory. Typically, D1-D3 systems in Type IIB string theory are studied because this system relates to the M2-M5 system by dimensional reduction and T-duality.

Self-dual string

For a membrane to end on a D5-brane, the membrane boundary must carry the charge of the self-dual field B on the five-brane worldvolume. There are different solutions to the field equations of B. For instance, a BPS solution was found [10] by looking at the supersymmetry transformation.

The linearised supersymmetry equation is

\delta_{\epsilon} \Omega^{j}_{\beta} = \epsilon^{\alpha i}(\frac{1}{2} (\gamma^{a})_{\alpha \beta}(\gamma_{b^{\prime}})^{j}_{i}\partial_a X^{b^{\prime}} - \frac{1}{6}(\gamma^{abc})_{\alpha \beta}\delta^{j}_i h_{abc}) = 0. \ \ (3)

Here b^{\prime}  labels transverse scalars, a indices label worldvolume directions, \alpha, \beta  denote spinor indices of spin(1,5), and i,j are spinor indices of USp(4)  . The solution balances the contribution of the 3-form field strength h with a contribution from the scalars. Additionally, the worldvolume of the string soliton can be taken to be in the 0,1 directions with all fields independent of x^0  and x^1  . An illustration of the solution is given below, showing an M2-brane ending on an M5-brane with a cross section S^3 \times \mathbb{R}  .

M2-branes ending on a M5-brane. The endpoint is a string. Courtesy of N. Copland, Aspects of M-Theory Brane Interactions and String Theory Symmetries [https://arxiv.org/abs/0707.1317].

As I am still trying to understand the calculation, I am currently looking at the following string solution

H_{01m} = \pm \frac{1}{4} \partial_m \phi,

H_{mnp} = \pm \frac{1}{4} \epsilon_{emnpq}\delta^{qr}\partial_r \phi,

\phi = \phi_0 + \frac{2Q}{\mid x - x_0 \mid^2}, \ \ (4)

where \phi  may be replaced by a more general superposition of solutions. We denote \pm Q as the magnetic and electric charge. There is a conformal factor in the full equations of motion which guarantees that they are satisfied even at x = x_0  , which means the solution is solitonic. This string soliton is said to possess its own anomalies that require cancellation (I assume Weyl, Lorentz). What is neat is that this string can be dimensionally reduced to get various T-duality configurations, which is something that would be fun to look into at some point down the road.

References

[1] D. Fiorenza, H. Sati, and U. Schreiber, The rational higher structure of m-theory. Fortschritte der Physik, 67(8-9):1910017, May 2019. [arXiv:1903.02834 [hep-th]].

[2] E. Witten, String theory dynamics in various dimensions. Nuclear PhysicsB, 443(1):85 – 126, 1995.

[3] E. Cremmer, B. Julia, and J. Scherk, Supergravity Theory in 11-dimensions. Phys. Lett. B76, No. 4, (409-412) 19 June 1978.

[4] S. Chester, S. Pufu, and X Yin, The M-Theory S-Matrix from ABJM: Beyond 11D supergravity. (2019). [arXiv:1804.00949v3 [hep-th]].

[5] A. Tseytlin, R4 terms in 11 dimensions and conformal anomaly of (2,0) theory. (2005). [arXiv:hep-th/0005072v4 [hep-th]].

[6] G. Russo, and A. Tseytlin, One-loop four-graviton amplitude in eleven-dimensional supergravity. (1997). [arXiv:hep-th/9707134v3 [hep-th]].

[7] P. Heslop, and A. Lipstein, M-theory Beyond The Supergravity Approximation. (2017). [arXiv:1712.08570 [hep-th]].

[8] P.K. Townsend, D-branes from M-branes. (1995). [arXiv:hep-th/9512062 [hep-th]].

[9] A. Strominger, \textit{Open p-branes}. Phys. Lett. B 383 (1996) 44. [arXiv:hep-th/9512059 [hep-th]].

[10] P.S. Howe, N.D. Lambert, and P.C. West, The self-dual string soliton. Nucl. Phys. B 515 (1998) 203. [arXiv:hep-th/9709014 [hep-th]].

[11] M. Perry and J.H. Schwarz, Interacting chiral gauge fields in six dimensions and Born-Infeld theory. Nucl. Phys. B 489 (1997) 47. [arXiv:hep-th/9611065 [hep-th]].

[12] D.S. Berman, Aspects of M-5 brane world volume dynamics. Phys. Lett. B 572 (2003) 101. [arXiv:hep-th/0307040 [hep-th]].

[13] J. Huerta, H. Sati, and U. Schreiber, Real ADE-equivariant (co)homotopy and Super M-branes. (2018). [arXiv:1805.05987 [hep-th]].

[14] N. Copland, Aspects of M-Theory Brane Interactions and String Theory Symmetries. [https://arxiv.org/abs/0707.1317].

[15] S. Palmer, Higher gauge theory and M-theory. [https://arxiv.org/abs/1407.0298].